It boils down to how to coexist and the cultivation of ethical principles and values that undergird such coexistence.

Europe has a wolf problem, but a Norwegian philosopher has the solution
Europeโs โwolf problemโ is fast becoming a source of social and political tension. Relativeย conservation successย across the continent has led to calls for action from worried politicians and farming and hunting groups. And the European Commission has now proposed aย change in their international status, from โstrictly protectedโ to โprotectedโ, which could allow people to hunt wolves.
However, changing the protection status may not be the best solution, especially as onlyย three of the nine wolf populationsย in the EU have reachedย favourable conservation status. Instead, perhaps the time is ripe for a renewed focus on learning to live โ again โ with wolves. Proven prevention strategies, such as fencing and the use of guard dogs, play a critical role in this.
But the question may be fundamentally philosophical. Namely, it boils down to how to coexist โ and the cultivation of ethical principles and values which undergird a successful coexistence.
โDeep ecologyโ and the equal right to exist
In this task, the work of Norwegian environmental philosopher Arne Nรฆss (1912-2009) might be of help. Nรฆss is known as the father of โdeep ecologyโ, an ethical theory that contends that all life has intrinsic value. Nรฆss argued that all beings, whether human or nonhuman, have an equal right to exist and flourish, a principle he called โbiospherical egalitarianismโ.
As this applies to wolves, Nรฆss was clear: wolves have just as much a right to be here as we do.
Nรฆss wrote anย essayย with biologist Ivar Mysterud stating: โThe well-being of the species wolf as part of human and nonhuman life on Earth has value in itself!โ As a result, they argued, โhumans have no right to reduce this richness and diversity, including wolf habitats and races, except to satisfy vital needs!โ
Despite this ostensibly radical challenge to human-centred ethical norms, Nรฆss demonstrated a pragmatic approach in how the principle of biospherical egalitarianism was applied in practice. For example, he considered the important contextual factors of local wolf-human interactions, writing:
For some sheep holders, the need to protect their sheep from wolves or to be in some way compensated is today vital. It means protecting the basis of their economy and home where they have lived for generations.
In addition to human interests, he also took seriously the moral obligation to reduce the suffering of sheep and other domestic animals. This is especially salient as humans have reduced the capacity of these species to evade wolves.
Mouflon, the wild ancestor of domestic sheep, do their best to avoid large predators by fleeing into mountains. In contrast, after thousands of years of selective breeding, modern livestock have fewer genetic defences and are left to fend for themselves in fenced-in fields.
Man has a heart, not just a brain
Nรฆss avoided a one-size-fits-all answer to the question of wolves (a position other scholarsย criticised him for). But his focus on articulating general ethical principles to serve as a backdrop for contextual decisions may have importance in the increasingly heated and political nature of this rewilding debate.
For example, Nรฆss used the termย โmixed communityโย to denote places which comprise humans and those species who play a clear role in human affairs. Challenging the tendency to define community only in human terms, Nรฆss contended that this framing helps to โbreak down some of the barriers commonly erected between humans and any other forms of life within our common spaceโ.
In doing so, this can open pathways for increased identification and empathy for nonhuman others โ a capacity Nรฆss believed all humans have, stemming from an inherent continuity between human and nonhuman life.
Indeed, as the pioneering American conservationistย Aldo Leopoldย similarly maintained, perceiving ourselves in a community with others is a prerequisite for moral action. In this case, it helps to make concrete the idea of a wolfโs right to exist โ they are members of the community just like us.
Applying this ethical framework of โmixed communitiesโ to current EU deliberations can have some benefits. For example, it may inspire the further development of creative, mutually beneficial solutions such as economic compensation for livestock losses โ a move which Nรฆss called for โ as well as improving wolf-attack prevention.
It may also play an effective role in countering the often-baseless fear and hysteria around wolves (Nรฆss blamed the brothers Grimm for the animalsโ bad public image).
Perhaps most important of all, though, is the potential for connecting with our emotional elements. As Nรฆss said: โMan has a heart, not only a brain.โ
To move towards a sustainable coexistence, it is not enough to appeal to abstractions about scientific benefits or devise perfectly efficient compensation schemes. This must also derive from a sense of solidarity with other species โ a full recognition that, in Nรฆssโs words: โHumans are not alone on this planet.โ
Interestingly, as aย recent studyย showed, most people living in rural communities in the EU already believe that wolves have a right to exist, corresponding with Nรฆssโs relative optimism about the possibility of mixed communities. This is all the more important to remember in light of the worrying political divisiveness in relation to Europeโs so-called wolf problem.
This article was written by Nora Ward, a lecturer in Philosophy at the University of Galway. It is republished from The Conversation under a Creative Commons license. Read the original article.
Did you like it? 4.5/5 (20)